next up previous
Next: References Up: No Title Previous: Decision Under Risk and

Nontransitive Preferences

A preference relation tex2html_wrap_inline1051 on a set X is nontransitive if there are tex2html_wrap_inline1701 for which tex2html_wrap_inline2895 and not tex2html_wrap_inline2897 , and is cyclic if there are tex2html_wrap_inline2899 with tex2html_wrap_inline2901 such that tex2html_wrap_inline2903 for all i < m and tex2html_wrap_inline2907 . The representations described thus far assume that tex2html_wrap_inline1051 is transitive, or at least acyclic. I believe that this reflects a strong attraction of decision theorists and perhaps others to transitivity as an intuitively obvious basis for rational thought and action, an apparently natural desire for order in practical affairs, and the supposed efficiency of optimization based on maximization. Although I find some merit in these contentions, I argue elsewhere (Fishburn 1991a) against transitivity as an undeniable tenet of rational preferences because I believe that reasonable people sometimes hold nontransitive or cyclic preference patterns that account for their true feelings.

My purpose here is not to recount the arguments for or against transitivity set forth in Fishburn (1991a). Instead, I will illustrate a few situations that might give rise to cyclic patterns and then describe four representations that can account for cyclic preferences by straightforward and elegant generalizations of representations that presume transitivity.

The genesis of cyclic patterns in decision theory may be Condorcet's (1785) phenomenon of cyclic majority. The simplest example uses candidates x,y and z and three voters with preference orders tex2html_wrap_inline2915 , tex2html_wrap_inline2917 and tex2html_wrap_inline2919 . Then, with tex2html_wrap_inline1051 the strict simple majority relation, tex2html_wrap_inline2923 . Arrow's (1950) famous extension shows that every reasonable rule for aggregating voters' preference orders that makes binary social comparisons without regard to other candidates' positions in voters' orders, and which allows a variety of voter preference profiles, must have profiles for which the social comparison relation is nontransitive. Subsequent contributions on this theme are reviewed in Fishburn (1987).

Multiattribute comparisons provide a source of cyclic preferences for an individual. May (1954) asked 62 college students to make binary comparisons between hypothetical marriage partners x,y and z characterized by three attributes, intelligence, looks and wealth:

x: very intelligence, plain, well off
y: intelligent, very good looking, poor
z: fairly intelligent, good looking, rich.

Seventeen of the 62 had the 2-to-1 majority cyclic pattern tex2html_wrap_inline2923 ; the other 45 had transitive preferences.

Let (a,p) denote the lottery that pays $a with probability p and nothing otherwise. Tversky (1969) observed that a significant number of people have the cyclic pattern

eqnarray528

In a four-state example with subjective probability of 1/4 for each state, consider four acts with monetary prizes:

states
   1    2    3    4
tex2html_wrap_inline1755 $10000 $9000 $8000 $7000
acts tex2html_wrap_inline2409 $9000 $8000 $7000 $10000
tex2html_wrap_inline2949 $8000 $7000 $10000 $9000
tex2html_wrap_inline2951 $7000 $10000 $9000 $8000

Subjective expected utility theory says that tex2html_wrap_inline2953 because every act is equivalent to a lottery with equal chances for the four prizes. However, some people will have tex2html_wrap_inline2955 because the first act in each tex2html_wrap_inline1051 comparison yields a larger prize than the second in three of the four states. Others may have the opposite cycle if they fear that they will experience severe regret if they choose the act with a $7000 prize in state i over the one with the $10000 prize in the same state and i turns out to be the state that obtains.

We now describe four representations that accommodate cyclic preferences. The first two apply to multiattribute situations, the third to lottery comparisons in decision under risk, and the fourth to act comparisons in decision under uncertainty.

Let tex2html_wrap_inline2963 and tex2html_wrap_inline2965 denote items described by n attributes. Assume that the attribute levels within a given attribute are unambiguously ordered by a weak order tex2html_wrap_inline2969 . The additive difference representation is

  equation906

where tex2html_wrap_inline1227 preserves tex2html_wrap_inline2969 as in (1) and tex2html_wrap_inline2975 is a strictly increasing functional on its domain with tex2html_wrap_inline2977 . Many possibilities for the tex2html_wrap_inline2975 allow tex2html_wrap_inline2895 and tex2html_wrap_inline2983 by way of positive sums on the right side of (15) for the three comparisons. Discussions and axioms for (15) and related representations are in Tversky (1969), Croon (1984), Chapter 17 in Suppes et al. (1989), and Fishburn (1992a).

An alternative to (15) is the nontransitive additive utility representation

  equation909

in which tex2html_wrap_inline2985 is a real-valued function on ordered pairs of levels of attribute i with tex2html_wrap_inline2989 and tex2html_wrap_inline2991 . Axioms for (16) are in Vind (1991) and Fishburn (1990, 1991b). The latter axiomatizations imply that each tex2html_wrap_inline2985 is skew symmetric, i.e.,

displaymath2995

and all three imply that the tex2html_wrap_inline2985 are unique up to proportionality transformations with a common scale multiplier.

Skew symmetry is also used in our other two representations. The representation for lotteries x and y on a set C of consequences is tex2html_wrap_inline3005 , where tex2html_wrap_inline2225 is a real-valued, skew-symmetric and bilinear function on ordered pairs of lotteries. Bilinearity means that tex2html_wrap_inline3009 and tex2html_wrap_inline3011 . We refer to the representation as the SSB representation, short for skew-symmetric and bilinear. When all individual consequences are in X and it is convex, we have the bilinear expected utility expression

displaymath3015

The SSB representation was first described in Kreweras (1961) and is axiomatized in Fishburn (1988), with tex2html_wrap_inline2225 unique up to a proportionality transformation. A constant-threshold SSB representation that has tex2html_wrap_inline3019 is axiomatized in Fishburn and Nakamura (1991).

Our final representation applies tex2html_wrap_inline1051 to a Savage act set tex2html_wrap_inline3023 for decision under uncertainty. The representation is

  equation912

where tex2html_wrap_inline2225 is a skew-symmetric functional on tex2html_wrap_inline3027 and tex2html_wrap_inline1809 is a finitely additive probability measure on tex2html_wrap_inline1783 , with tex2html_wrap_inline1809 unique and tex2html_wrap_inline2225 unique up to a proportionality transformation. When tex2html_wrap_inline2225 decomposes as tex2html_wrap_inline3039 , (17) reduces to Savage's subjective expected utility representation. Axioms that imply (17) for all acts that use only finite numbers of consequences are in Chapter 9 in Fishburn (1988). They are like Savage's axioms in most respects with weak order replaced by an asymmetry condition. Extension to all acts is also discussed in Chapter 9. Other representations that are closely related to (17) appear in Loomes and Sugden (1987), Fishburn and LaValle (1987) and Fishburn (1988).

Although cyclic preference patterns have been studied in depth for aggregate relations in voting and social choice theory, they have received very little attention in individual decision theory. Unlike most decision theorists, I think the aversion to cyclic preferences for individuals is unjustified, and I hope that more will be done on the subject in the years ahead.


next up previous
Next: References Up: No Title Previous: Decision Under Risk and

Peter.Fishburn